Oldalképek
PDF
ePub

Cock's fellow constable. The former, however, stated he saw nobody immediately after he heard the shots. A pistol has recently been found, thirty-one years after the crime, thrown into a pit on the scene of the Whalley Range murder, but in a direction opposite to that in which Peace declared he fled. .. The sequence of events after the con

fession of Peace was that Mr. Cross, then Home Secretary, stated in the House of Commons that he had felt it his duty to advise the Crown to grant a free pardon to William Habron, and that in this course he had entire concurrence of both the learned judge who tried the case and also of the law officers of the Crown.

1

128. MADELEINE SMITH'S CASE. Evidence. Amer. ed. 1905. p. 300.) 1 In a case of the deepest interest, in 1857, before the High Court of Justiciary at Edinburgh, a question whether or not the prisoner had the opportunity of administering arsenic to the deceased was the turning point of the case. The prisoner, a young girl of nineteen, was tried upon an indictment charging her, in accordance with the law of Scotland, with the administration to the same person of arsenic, with intent to murder, on two several occasions in the month of February, and with his murder by the same means on the 22d of March following.

(W. WILLS. Circumstantial

she should marry no other person while he lived. After the failure of her efforts to obtain the return of her letters, she resumed in her correspondence her former tone of passionate affection, assuring him that she would marry him and no one else, and denying that there was any truth in the rumors of her connection with another. She appointed a meeting on the night of the 19th of February, at her father's house, where she was in the habit of receiving his visits, after the family had retired to rest, telling him that she wished to have back her "cool letters," apparently with the intention of inducing him to believe that she remained constant in her attachment to him. In the middle of the night after that interview, at which he had taken coffee prepared by the prisoner, L'Angelier was seized with alarming illness, the symptoms of which were similar to those of poisoning by arsenic. There was no evidence that the prisoner possessed arsenic at that time, but on the 21st she purchased a large quantity, professedly for the purpose of poisoning rats, an excuse for which there was no pretense. On the night of the 22d, L'Angelier again visited the prisoner, and about eleven o'clock on the following day was seized with the same alarming symptoms as before; and on this occasion also he had taken cocoa from the hands of the prisoner. After this attack L'An[For a citation of the full report of this trial, see Appendix.]

She had returned home from a boarding school in 1853, and in the following year formed a clandestine connection with a foreigner of inferior position, named L'Angelier, whose addresses had been forbidden by her parents. Early in 1856 their intercourse assumed an unlawful character, as was shown by her letters. In the month of December following, another suitor appeared, whose addresses were accepted by her with the consent of her parents, and arrangements were made for their marriage in June. During the earlier part of this engagement, the prisoner kept up her interviews and correspondence with L'Angelier; but the correspondence gradually became cooler, and she expressed to him her determination to break off the connection, and implored him to return her letters; but this he refused to do, and declared that

gelier continued extremely ill, and was advised to go from home for the recovery of his health.

On the 6th of March the prisoner a second time bought arsenic; and on the same day she went with her family to the Bridge of Allan (where she was visited by her accepted lover), and remained till the 17th, when they returned to Glasgow. On the day before her departure for the Bridge of Allan L'Angelier wrote a letter to her. To this letter, the prisoner replied from the Bridge of Allan, that . . . she would answer all his questions when they met, and informed him of her expected return to Glasgow on the 17th of March. L'Angelier, pursuant to medical advice, on the 10th of March went to Edinburgh, leaving directions for the transmission of his letters, and having become much better, left that place on the 19th for the Bridge of Allan. . .

[ocr errors]

A letter from the prisoner to L'Angelier came to his lodgings on Saturday the 21st, from the date and contents of which it appeared that she had written a letter appointing to see him on the 19th; he had not, however, received it in time to enable him to keep her appointment. In that letter she urged him to come to see her, and added, "I waited and waited for you, but you came not. I shall wait again to-morrow night, same time and arrangement.' This letter was immediately transmitted to L'Angelier, and in consequence he returned to his lodgings at Glasgow about eight o'clock on the evening of Sunday the 22d, in high spirits and improved health, having traveled a considerable distance by railway, and walked fifteen miles. He left his lodgings about nine o'clock, and was seen going leisurely in the direction of the prisoner's house, and about twenty minutes past nine he called at the house of an acquaintance who lived about four or five minutes' walk from the prisoner's residence. After leaving his

friend's house, all trace of him was lost, until two o'clock in the morning, when he was found at the door of his lodgings, unable to open the latch, doubled up and speechless from pain and exhaustion, and about eleven o'clock the same morning he died, from the effects of arsenic, of which an enormous quantity was found in his body.

The prisoner stated in her declaration that she had been in the habit of using arsenic as a cosmetic, and denied that she had seen the deceased on that eventful night; whether she had done so or not was the all-momentous question. . .

As to the principal charge of murder, his Lordship said, "Supposing you are quite satisfied that the prisoner's letter brought L'Angelier again into Glasgow, are you in a situation to say, with satisfaction to your consciences, as an inevitable and just result from this, that the prisoner and deceased met that night? that is the point in the case. It is for you to say whether it has been proved that L'Angelier was in the house that night. ..

[ocr errors]

'If you think they met together that night, and he was seized and taken ill, and died of arsenic, the symptoms beginning shortly after the time he left her, it will be for you to say whether in that case there is any doubt as to whose hand administered the poison.

"And I say there is no doubt but it is a matter for you to consider - that after writing this letter he might expect she would wait another night, and therefore it was very natural that he should go to see her that Sunday night.

"But this is an inference only. . . In drawing an inference, you must always look to the important character of the inference which you are asked to draw. If this had been an appointment about business, and you found that a man came to Glasgow for the purpose of seeing another upon business, and that he

went out for that purpose, having no other object in coming to Glasgow, you would probably scout the notion of the person whom he had gone to meet, saying, 'I never saw or heard of him that day'; but here you are asked to draw the inference that they met upon that night, where the fact of their meeting is the foundation of a charge of murder. You must feel, therefore, that the drawing of an inference in the ordinary matters of civil business, or in the actual intercourse of mutual friends, is one thing, and the inference from the fact that he came to Glasgow, that they did meet, and that, therefore, the poison was administered to him by her at that time, is another, and a most enormous jump in the category of inferences. Now, the question for you to put to yourselves is this Can you now, with satisfaction to your own minds, come to the conclusion that they did meet on that occasion, the result being, and the object of coming to that conclusion being, to fix upon her the administration of the arsenic by which he died?... You may be perfectly satisfied that L'Angelier did not commit suicide; and of course it is necessary for you to be satisfied of that before you could find that anybody administered arsenic to him. Probably none of you will think for a moment that he went out that

night and that, without seeing her, and without knowing what she wanted to see him about, he swallowed about 200 grains of arsenic in the street, and that he was carrying it about with him. Probably you will discard such an idea altogether, . . . yet, on the other hand, keep in view that that will not of itself establish that the prisoner administered the poison. . . .

"Therefore if you cannot say, We find here satisfactory evidence of this meeting, and that the poison must have been administered by her at a meeting whatever may be your suspicion, however heavy the weight and load of suspicion is against her, and however you may have to struggle to get rid of it, you perform the best and bounden duty as a jury to separate suspicion from truth, and to proceed upon nothing that you do not find established in evidence against her."

The jury returned, in conformity with the law of Scotland, a verdict of not guilty on the first, and of not proven on the second and third charges. On the supposition that the parties met on the fatal evening in question, there could be but one conclusion as to the guilt of the prisoner, the hypothesis of suicide being considered by the learned Judge as out of the question, as it obviously was.

129. O'BANNON v. VIGUS. [Printed post, as No. 383.]

Topic 4. Habit (Usage, Custom)

130. JAMES SULLY. The Human Mind. (1892. Vol. II, p. 224.) Habit is a product of acquisition. In this respect it differs from instinct, with which otherwise it has much in common. We say we do a thing from habit, e.g. nod back when a person not recognized nods to us, when as a consequence of long practice and frequent repetition the action has become in a measure organized, and thus shorn of some of its original appanage of full consciousness or attention. The characteristic note of habit is mechanicality. In its most forcible manifestation habitual movement approaches to a subconscious reflex, as in the case just referred to. . . . It is thus evident

that in habit we have in a particular way to do with that lapse of the intenser degrees of consciousness which accompanies an approximation of nervous structures to a state of perfect adjustment to the environment. The oft-repeated action becomes habitual and so automatic because the nervous centers engaged have taken on special modifications, have, according to the customary physiological figure, become "seamed" by special lines of discharge. The perfect fixation of a habit appears to liberate the highest cortical centers from all but the slightest measure of cooperation in the process, the greater part of the central work (transmission of a definite kind of afferent excitation into a definite path of motor discharge) being now carried out by help of stably fixed arrangements in subordinate centers. . . . The on-coming of habit is shown by two principal criteria. First of all, repetition of movement tends to remove all sense of effort and to render the movement easy. . . . In the second place, habit involves and manifests itself in a consolidation of the processes of association involved. One of the most familiar characteristics of habit is prompt succession of a movement on the recurrence of the idea of a desired object. Here the intermediate idea of the movement itself is repressed or skipped. . . . A further and more striking result of this fixing of associative connection is the coordination of particular sense presentations with appropriate motor-responses. This is illustrated in the recurring movements of everyday life, as taking out a latchkey on approaching one's door. Where this process is complete there lapses not only the initiative idea of the movement, but even the idea of procurable object. Thus when a man automatically winds up his watch on taking it out of his pocket during the operation of dressing for dinner, the action seems to be wanting in all ideational initiation. .

Habit and Chains of Movement. As we saw when dealing with the process of association, series of movements tend by repetition to grow consolidated, so that each step calls up the succeeding ones without a distinct intervention of consciousness. Simple examples of this are to be found in the series of movements involved in walking, dressing, and undressing, in playing a piece of music from memory, reciting a familiar poem, and so forth. Such chains of movement approximate in their lack of clear consciousness, their mechanical regularity, and promptness of succession to the motor sequences in breathing, and other primarily automatic movements. What differentiates such habitual chains from primarily automatic successions is the initial volitional impulse. I must consciously and voluntarily start the walking, the dressing, and so forth. But the start is all, so far as volition is concerned. The succession then takes care of itself, and, what is more, is carried out better for the non-intervention of attention.

...

Degrees of Habitual Coördination. It follows from our general definition of the principle, that habit shows itself in very unlike degrees of strength. The process of organic attachment is more or less complete in the case of different movements. We may now glance at these differences in the strength of habit, and seek to determine their conditions. We may estimate the prompting force of habit in more ways than one. The obvious index to its influence is lapse of physical initiation as seen in the swiftness of the motor response. All the popular examples of habit, as the story of the victimized soldier who dropped his dinner at the word "Attention!”

shouted by some practical jokers, illustrate this feature. The swifter the response to a particular sense stimulus, the more of force of habit is there indicated. Another criterion is specialty or precision of response.. The soldier's loss of his dinner was due to the unerring precision of the habitual reaction, the swift dropping of the arms into the vertical line on the recurrence of the customary signal. The stronger the habit, the more definite or exact will be the response. Another measure of strength of habit closely connected with the preceding is uniformity, or unfailingness of response whenever the proper stimulus occurs. This criterion, together with speciality or definiteness, gives to habit its unvarying and monotonous character, its resemblance to the actions of a machine, and to those lower nervous reflexes which come nearest to mechanical actions. Lastly, the strength of a habit is directly measurable in terms of the difficulty of modify ing it by special volitional effort. Half-formed habits can be easily altered; wholly formed, only by dint of extraordinary volitional effort. Employing such criteria, we can draw up a scale of habitual movement. . . . The main conditions on which these varying degrees of habit depend appear to be the following: (1) The amount of time and attention given to the particular movement or combination of movements so as to make it our own. Since habit is superinduced on a volitional process, it is evident that the action must first be perfectly acquired through a conscious process of acquisition. (2) The frequency with which the particular stimulus has been followed by the particular movement. This condition, repetition, or frequency of performance, is the great determinate of strength of habit. (3) The unbroken uniformity of past responses. By this is meant that a particular stimulus S should have always been followed by a particular motor reaction M, not sometimes followed, at other times not, or followed by another sort of movement, as M'. This condition evidently goes to determine the degree of unfailingness, as also of specialization in the habit. Thus, children who are sometimes required to do a certain thing by their parents, but now and again allowed to intermit the action, never acquire perfect habits.

131. HANS GROSS. Criminal Psychology. (1911. transl. Kallen, § 28, p. 158.) We have yet to ask what is meant by "rule" and what its relation is to probability. Scientifically "rule" means law subjectively taken, and is of equal significance with the guiding line for one's own conduct, whence it follows that there are only rules of art and morality, but no rules of nature. Usage does not imply this interpretation. We say that as a rule it hails only in the daytime; by way of exception, in the night also; the rule for the appearance of whales indicates that they live in the Arctic Ocean; a general rule indicates that bodies that are especially soluble in water should dissolve more easily in warm than in cold water, but salt dissolves equally well in both. Again we say: As a rule the murderer is an unpunished criminal; it is a rule that the brawler is no thief and vice versa; the gambler is as a rule a man of parts, etc. We may say, therefore, that regularity is equivalent to customary recurrence and that whatever serves as rule may be expected as probable. If, i.e. it be said, that this or that happens as a rule, we may suppose that it will repeat itself this time. It is not permissible to expect more. But it frequently happens that we mistake rules

« ElőzőTovább »